Charlie Gard: Doing the right thing for the right reasons

That is the heading on a press release from the Anscombe Bioethics Centre, a Roman Catholic academic institute in Oxford that engages with the moral questions arising in clinical practice and biomedical research.

Charlie Gard is a baby, born 11 months ago in UK, who has a serious and rare genetic condition, for which there is no proven cure. For eight months he has received treatment at Great Ormond Street Hospital in London; staff there are convinced that Charlie has no chance of recovery. Charlie’s parents refute this and are convinced Charlie responds to their voices and touch, and that he has far more awareness of the world around him than the professionals believe. They do not accept the view of the professionals at GOSH that his condition is irreversible. Over £1 million has been raised to support them in their quest.

A judge ruled that Charlie should have life supports withdrawn. The case has gone through the courts, right to the UK Supreme Court and to the European Court of Human Rights, all going against the parents. It has drawn in Pope Francis and President Donald Trump.

It highlights important ethical questions about how to decide what is right in such a situation, and who should make the decisions. Should the final decision be that of the parents? Is it right that the decision be taken over by the health system or the justice system, despite the view of the parents?

It seems an anomaly in the context of 190,406 procured abortions in England and Wales in 2016 (government statistics). For a child with a condition like Charlie’s, an abortion could have been carried out right up to the time of birth. It contrasts also with the 56.3 million procured abortions worldwide each year – 107 every minute. And there is the context of the living conditions of so many children around the world, and their great needs. World Health Organisation reports that the number of neonatal deaths was 2.7 million in 2015;  5.9 million children under the age of 5 years died in 2015.

However I might answer such questions when Charlie’s case is elsewhere, I also ask myself whether my decision would be different if Charlie was my child or my grandchild, or my next-door neighbour.

The Anscombe Centre Press Release makes a good distinction in relation to the court proceedings: “opinions were also cited in court that seem to refer not to the worthwhileness of treatment but to the worthwhileness of Charlie’s life… This way of reasoning can have dangerous and far reaching implications and should be repudiated firmly.”

What can we learn about the value we recognise in each human life? As we face a referendum on the Eighth Amendment, can we learn something in relation to unborn children with life-limiting conditions? As the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child says: “in accordance with the principles proclaimed in the Charter of the United Nations, recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world… the child, by reason of his physical and mental immaturity, needs special safeguards and care, including appropriate legal protection, before as well as after birth.”

Pádraig McCarthy

 

Anscombe Bioethics Centre Press Release, 5 July 2017.

Charlie Gard: Doing the right thing for the right reason.

See http://www.bioethics.org.uk/images/user/charliegardstatement.pdf.

On 27 June 2017, the European Court of Human Rights endorsed the judgements of the UK courts in the Charlie Gard case.

The UK courts had upheld the view of the doctors caring for Charlie that it was no longer in his best interests to continue artificial ventilation. The UK courts had also ruled that it would not be in Charlie’s best interest to undergo experimental “nucleoside therapy” in America as this had no realistic prospect of benefit and might have added to his distress.

This is indeed a heart-rending case. The condition from which Charlie Gard suffers is incurable and progressive: even with aggressive treatment he would be unlikely to live for more than a few months.[1] The suffering of the parents in this situation has been compounded by the long legal dispute over what form of treatment would be best for Charlie.

Ethical analysis

There are two things that need to be kept in mind in end of life care: respecting life and accepting death.

Respecting life means that every person must be valued for as long as they live. One implication of this is that (at least in a medical context) death should never be the aim of our action or of our inaction. We should never try to bring about or to hasten death.

On the other hand, accepting death means that we should prepare properly for death – our own and that of other people. One implication of this is that we should not deny the reality of the situation or flee from the inevitable by seeking every possible intervention, however disproportionate.[2]

While every human life is worthy of respect, not every treatment is worth pursuing. This may be

  • because it no longer serves its purpose (it is futile),
  • or because it is excessively burdensome: the burdens may be physical, psychological, social, or economic,
  • or because it promises too little benefit relative to the burdens it entails.[3]

Good reasons and bad

In the case of Charlie Gard, the doctors caring for him believed that he could probably experience pain, but was “unable to react to it in a meaningful way”. [4]

Their evidence was that “being ventilated, being suctioned, living as Charlie does, are all capable of causing pain”.[5] It was said that “even before Charlie began to suffer from seizures on 15th December 2016, the clinical consensus was that his quality of life was so poor that he should not be subject to long term ventilation”.[6]

The statements that ventilation could itself be causing suffering and that it was producing only a poor “quality of life” (i.e. state of health and well-being) together constitute an argument about whether this particular treatment is worthwhile. Others may argue with the conclusion, but this way of reasoning is ethically defensible.

On the other hand, opinions were also cited in court that seem to refer not to the worthwhileness of treatment but to the worthwhileness of Charlie’s life.

In the High Court, Mr Justice Francis repeatedly stated, with approval, that “Charlie’s parents accept that his present quality of life is one that is not worth sustaining”.[7] Francis J also cited one doctor as saying that the severity of Charlie’s condition was such that “it could be argued that Charlie would derive no benefit from continued life”.[8]

At best, these are muddled ways of referring to the limited benefits of treatment relative to the burdens. At worst, they express a judgement that life with some disabilities is not worth living at all (the life is “not worth sustaining”). This way of reasoning can have dangerous and far reaching implications and should be repudiated firmly.

Another criticism which could be levelled at the way the UK courts approached this case is that they treated Charlie as if he had no parents or as if his parents had already been shown to be acting in a very unreasonable, albeit well-meaning way.

In a case like this, the first question should not be “What treatment would be in the best interests of Charlie?”, as though making a parental decision on his behalf, but “Are Charlie’s mother and father acting reasonably or at least, not very unreasonably?”

Only after parents have been shown to be acting or seeking to act very unreasonably and exposing their child to a risk of significant harm, albeit with good intentions, should such decisions be taken out of their hands.

Flawed reasoning, defensible decisions

There are flaws, therefore, in the way that the courts came to their decisions in the Charlie Gard case, both in negative value judgements made (or cited with apparent approval) on the  worthwhileness of Charlie’s life and in a failure to recognise the role and status of his parents.

Nevertheless, the final decisions in this case – to withdraw ventilation and not to seek experimental treatment – are decisions that parents in this situation could reasonably make on behalf of their child. The decisions themselves are morally defensible. The Catholic moral tradition does not oblige the use of medical procedures that are burdensome, dangerous, extraordinary, or disproportionate to their expected outcome.[9]

At some point we will all die, and often we will be undergoing medical treatment before we die, and as the chances of improvement fade and the time remaining grows short, the burdens and side effects of the treatment are a reason to forego intrusive and extraordinary means and to focus on symptom control.

This is true of dying children just as much as dying adults.  There is a time to fight and a time to cease from fighting.

The staff of the Anscombe Bioethics Centre wish to express our solidarity with Charlie’s parents as they go through this deeply painful time and assure them of our prayers for Charlie and for all those around him.

The Anscombe Bioethics Centre (originally known as the Linacre Centre for Healthcare Ethics) is a Roman Catholic academic institute based in Britain, that engages with the moral questions arising in clinical practice and biomedical research.

<F0B5E330205E4F588C6BBF5E5686A1EE.png>

[1] For more on Charlie Gard’s medical condition see the website of Great Ormond Street Hospital. http://www.gosh.nhs.uk/frequently-asked-questions-about-charlie-gard-court-case

[2] Catholic Bishops’ Conference of England and Wales. A Practical Guide to the Spiritual Care of the Dying Person. London: Catholic Truth Society, 2010, paragraph 2.1http://www.bioethics.org.uk/images/user/guide-spiritual-caredying-person.pdf

[3] The Ethics of Care of the Dying Person Anscombe Bioethics Centre, 2013. http://www.bioethics.org.uk/images/user/TheEthicsofCareoftheDyingPersonwebsite.pdf

[4] Great Ormond Street Hospital v Yates and others [2017] EWHC 972 (Fam), 22.

[5] Ibid., 22.

[6] Ibid., 59.

[7] Ibid., 48, 14, 61.

[8] Ibid., 60, emphasis added. Such negative judgements are also reflected in problematic language used in the current guidance issued by the Royal College of Paediatrics and Child Health. See Larcher V, Craig F, Bhogal K, et al. “Making decisions to limit treatment in life-limiting and life-threatening conditions in children: a framework for practice”. Archives of Disease in Childhood 2015;100:s1-s23, cited in the judgement.

[9] Catechism of the Catholic Church, paragraph 2278; see Catholic Bishops’ Conference of England and Wales. A Practical Guide to the Spiritual Care of the Dying Person. London: Catholic Truth Society, 2010, paragraph 2.4.

 

Similar Posts

2 Comments

Join the Discussion

Keep the following in mind when writing a comment

  • Your comment must include your full name, and email. (email will not be published). You may be contacted by email, and it is possible you might be requested to supply your postal address to verify your identity.
  • Be respectful. Do not attack the writer. Take on the idea, not the messenger. Comments containing vulgarities, personalised insults, slanders or accusations shall be deleted.
  • Keep to the point. Deliberate digressions don't aid the discussion.
  • Including multiple links or coding in your comment will increase the chances of it being automati cally marked as spam.
  • Posts that are merely links to other sites or lengthy quotes may not be published.
  • Brevity. Like homilies keep you comments as short as possible; continued repetitions of a point over various threads will not be published.
  • The decision to publish or not publish a comment is made by the site editor. It will not be possible to reply individually to those whose comments are not published.